Printed in Outlines:
Critical Social studies, 2005, 7, № 1, 31-50
Nikolai
Veresov
Ph. D. Research Director
"Russian culture and language project"
University of Oulu
Teacher Training Department in Kajaani,
87101,
It was not only Marxism which
influenced Vygotsky. He was a child of the Silver Age of Russian culture and
philosophy and the influence of this should not be underestimated. Some traits in Vygotsky’s
theory, traditionally considered as Marxist – such as the concept of the social
origins of mind or sign as psychological tool have deeper and wider roots in
works of Shpet, Blonsky, Sorokin and Meierhold.
As for Marxism as such, it must be mentioned that during
all three periods of his creative evolution Vygotsky had different approaches
to what was true Marxist psychology and how it should be built. These are items
this paper is focused on.
Marxist
philosophy undoubtedly exerted a great influence on various aspects of
Vygotsky’s ideas. Marxist sources in Vygotsky’s cultural-historical psychology
constitute a major theme in discussions of Soviet (Atramonov, 1994; Davydov
& Radzikhovskii, 1985), modern Russian (Asmolov, 1998; Leont’ev, 2003;
Yaroshevsky, 1992), and Western literature (Elhammoumi, 2001; Jensen, 1999;
Lee, 1985; Seve, 1999; Tolman, 2001; Wertsch, 1981, 1983, 1985b;),
Thus, S. Toulmin notes that
it should be evident, that
Vygotsky’s...quotations from Marxist fathers, and¼ respectful references to Marx and
Engels...represent something more than hagiography or political lip service...
Vygotsky was more than happy to call himself a Marxist. And in any event,
leaving all political issues aside, the general frame provided by ‘historical
materialist’ philosophy gave him the basis he needed for developing an
integrated account of the relations between developmental psychology and
clinical neurology, cultural anthropology and the psychology of art (Toulmin,
1978, p. 51-57.)
In Western literature this general position was supported in a number
of ways (see Cole & Scribner, 1978; Wertsch, 1981; Wertsch, 1985a, and
others).
At the
same time modern literature gives an essentially contradictory picture of Vygotsky
and Marxism. Thus, according to F. Newman and L. Hotlzman, he was a scientific
father of Marxist psychology in Soviet Union (Newman & Holzman, 1993) while
J. Bruner claims that his Marxism was “closer to Althusser, Habermas and the
Frankfurt School than to the Soviet Marxism of his times or of ours” (Bruner,
1987, p.2).
Thus,
when we speak about Vygotsky and Marxism we should ask what kind of Marxism we
mean? Is it the Marxism of Marx or the diametrically opposed to each other
Marxism of Althusser and Habermas? Perhaps we mean Marxism of Trotsky[1] or even
that of V. Lenin. Most likely we mean Marxism in the spirit of E. Ilyenkov
(Bakhurst, 1991, Jones, 2000; Jones, 2001).
Such a
contradictory picture indicates a lack of historical perspective in approaching
the cultural-historical theory of Vygotsky. His approach and methods changed their focus from reflexes
in the early writings (1917-1924), through social behaviour (1925-1927) to the
later works which exemplify a truly cultural-historical approach (see Tudge,
1999, p. 11-17). Any attempt to find a cultural-historical theory amidst the
pre-1928 writings of Vygotsky would be futile. Not
every thought of Vygotsky could be attributed to his famous theory, and what is
more, there are some traits within his theory, which are mistakenly identified
as exclusively Marxist. In uncovering the nature of the relation between
Marxism and Vygotsky we must address dramatic and even tragic elements.
Vygotsky’s philosophical orientation was
wider than Marxism. Indeed, his first insights into the problems of the
personality and human consciousness were philosophical rather than
psychological. Rather than I. Pavlov or K. Marx it is V. Soloviev, N. Berdiaev, A. Belyi and the Russian
symbolists, A. Potebnya, W. Humboldt, W. Shakespeare, O.
Mandelshtam, V. Shklovsky, Yu. Aikhenvald, G. Shpet, P. Blonsky and many others
who form his social and cultural environment and act as participants in his
scientific dialogues.
Given
such a background it is worth examining how Vygotsky himself explained the
relationship between his psychology and Marxism. What were his thoughts on
Marxist psychology? What were his views on these relations and how did these
views change? Is it possible to find in Vygotsky’s original texts a sort of “formula”
expressing his view on what was Marxist psychology? In other words, discovering
the problem of Vygotsky and Marxism, it obviously makes sense to take into
account his own opinion on that matter.
At the same time the influence of the ‘Silver Age’ of Russian culture[2] on
Vygotsky is also of interest. It is on these issues which the present paper
concentrates.
Vygosky’s
creative evolution may be divided into three periods. Each of these was
characterised by Vygotsky’s developing approach to what is (and what is not)
Marxist psychology. In contrast to the widespread discussions in the literature
of the ‘classical’
At
least three works, namely, Pedagogical Psychology, Psychology of Art (written
between 1917 and 1924) and Methods of Reflexological and Psychological
Investigation (1926) are of importance for that period of Vygotsky’s
theoretical evolution.
The
first two of these represent the reflexological approach to the human mind.
“The theory of...reflexes is the basis upon which a new psychology must be
built.” (Vygotsky, 1926b, p.7)[3]. The
concept of reflex (a modification of I. Pavlov’s ideas which includes ‘speech
reflex’) was the basic explanatory principle. The human mind and consciousness
(thoughts and emotions) were viewed as a system of inhibited speech reflexes.
In brief, Vygotsky approached reflexology (Pavlov’s and Behterev’s) as
materialist (Marxist) psychology. Thus, human consciousness becomes nothing more
than the specific “reflex of reflexes” (Vygotsky, 1926b, p.45).
The third important work of that period was his famous report, Methods
of Reflexological Research Applied to the Study of the Psyche, presented at the
Second All-Russian Congress on Psychoneurology in
A. A. Leont’ev gives the reason for this important event in Vygotsky’s
life in terms of his Marxist orientation which attracted the attention of K. N.
Kornilov. In accordance with the official task of the young members of staff of
the Moscow Psychological Institute (Leont’ev, A., 1996, p. 7), Kornilov sought
to develop Marxist psychology. In order to clarify the background to these
events it is worthwhile considering the state of Soviet psychology at that
time.
Those years were characterised by strenuous debates and arguments
concerning such problems as the relationship between subjective and objective
methods of analysis, or between introspection and ‘extraspection’. One such
argument pitted reflexology against psychology. Debates concentrated around
such issues as reductionism, antireductionism and the systemic analysis of
mental phenomena. In his report Vygotsky formulated his own theoretical
position with respect to those arguments. We may be sure that the appearance at
the Petrograd Congress rostrum of an obscure provincial teacher was received,
despite his striking and original report, as yet another attempt to support the
position of K. Kornilov and his followers in the struggle between the
reflexologists and the psychologists.
The purpose of the report was to combine reflexology (the objective
scientific method of analysis) with psychology (the science of the subjective
internal world of the individual) to form a single science - the objective psychology of consciousness. Vygotsky even
described himself as “more of a reflexologist than Pavlov” (Vygotsky, 1926a, p.
42).
In his report, Vygotsky did not touch on Marxism as such but his acute
criticism on the one hand of empirical subjective psychology and on the other
of reflexology impressed the representatives of the new psychological party,
which was searching for objective methods of studying consciousness. We could
even say that it was not Marxism in Vygotsky’s report and theoretical position
which attracted the attention of Kornilov’s group; what was really original in
Vygotsky’s views at that time might be encapsulated by the words monism and materialism. In considering the possibilities of creating a
monistic materialistic theory of consciousness on the basis of reflexology
(i.e. ‘materialistic psychology’) Vygotsky compared classical methods of
reflexological analysis with classical methods of psychological analysis and
contrived to unify these two sciences into one based on methods of objective
materialistic methods (Vygotsky, 1982, p. 60-62).
Summarising our brief overview of Vygotsky’s position during this first
period we note that the formula of consciousness as a “reflex of reflexes” is
quite far removed from the main ideas of the cultural-historical theory. As for
Marxism in psychology, Vygotsky was not the only one of Russian psychologists
who considered reflexology as a materialist (Marxist) psychology since it was
the only basis for creating a monistic materialistic theory of human
consciousness. It should be mentioned, on the other hand, that very soon he
became disappointed with this “formula” since, on his opinion, the concept of
reflex could not become the fundamental concept of psychology as a concrete
science of human behaviour. The contradiction between the objective methods of
analysis of human mind Vygotsky was searching for, and the reflex as basic
concept, was the moving force forwarding Vygotsky’s thought to the second
period of development of his theoretical views.
There
are two works of Vygotsky reflecting this new stage of his thoughts during the
second period from 1925 to 1927. They are Consciousness as a Problem in the
Psychology of Behaviour (1925) and A Historical Sense of Psychological Crisis
(1927).
As a result of various adverse technical and organisational
circumstances Consciousness as a Problem in the Psychology of Behaviour
appeared in 1925 before the written version of the
According to V. Davydov and L. Radzikhovskii, Vygotsky “formulated
three programmes” in that article for the study of consciousness. These were
(1) consciousness is a reflex of reflexes, (2) consciousness is a question of
the structure of behaviour, and (3) consciousness is a feature of human labour
activity (Davydov & Radzikhovskii, 1985, p. 45-48). Moreover, “in
Vygotsky's third programme...consciousness emerged as an aspect of the
structure of labour activity” and this programme (in contrast to the first two)
was of decisive significance “relying directly on Marx’s ideas” (Davydov &
Radzikhovskii, 1985, p. 48).
Let us
again take a look at the text. There are two places in the article where
Vygotsky borrowed directly from Marxism. Firstly, in speaking about Marx’s
famous illustrations of the spider and the architect, Vygotsky noted that
“Marx’s explanation, which is beyond dispute, means nothing more than a doubling of experience that is
compulsory for human labour” (Vygotsky, 1925, p. 183).
Secondly,
when discussing the point of instinctive behaviour in animals, Vygotsky wrote,
“The spider that weaves his web and the bee that builds his cell out of wax do
this out of instinct, mechanically, always in the same way, and in doing so
they never display any more activity than in any other adaptive reactions.”
(Vygotsky, 1982, p. 84)[4] This for
Vygotsky was no more than a simple illustration of the process of ‘active
adaptation’ in humans, which has of course nothing in common with
“consciousness as a feature of human labour activity”.
What
are the main features of Vygotsky’s programme of studying consciousness? Let us
briefly examine the article:
1.
In contrast to his own
previous views Vygotsky sharply criticised even the very possibility of any
reflexological explanation of the consciousness.
“A reflex is an abstract concept;
methodologically it is extremely valuable, but it cannot become the fundamental
concept of psychology as a concrete science of human behaviour... We should
beware of any direct transportation of reflexological laws into psychology...We
ought to study not reflexes, but behaviour, its mechanism, its component parts,
and its structure. Actually, what we are studying in every case is behaviour,
since we invariably organise beforehand, in some way or other, the behaviour
of the subject in order to ensure that this or that reaction or reflex will
dominate; otherwise, we would achieve nothing.” (Vygotsky, 1925, pp. 179 -181).
2.
Therefore,
“...the problem of consciousness must
be solved in psychology in a sense that consciousness is an interaction,
reflection, and mutual excitation of different systems of reflexes. What is
conscious is what is transmitted as an irritant to other systems in which it
has a response. Consciousness is always an echo, a response apparatus.”
(Vygotsky, 1925, p. 187.)
3. “The individual aspect of consciousness is constructed as derived
and secondary, based on the social and exactly according to its model.”
(Vygotsky, 1925, p. 196) Moreover, citing here Paul Natorp (but not K. Marx),
Vygotsky adds, “This is very close to the division of the individual person
into an ‘Ego’ and an ‘Id’, which S. Freud analytically describes. (Vygotsky,
1925, p. 196) Furthermore, Vygotsky saw the connection between the individual
consciousness and the social mechanisms of communications within the framework
of social behaviour in terms of reversible reflex. “It is extremely important
here to establish, if only in passing, that... the mechanism of social
behaviour and the mechanism of consciousness are the same. Speech...is a
system of... reflexes of consciousness, a system for reflecting other systems.”
(Vygotsky, 1925, p. 195.)
One can see that Vygotsky’s approach is very close to that of the social behaviourists: consciousness is a relation between social reactions according to social models.
Thus, not three but only one scientific programme of studying
consciousness was presented. Moreover, there appear to be insufficient grounds
for speaking of a “programme of studying the consciousness as a feature of
human labour activity” relying directly on Marx’s ideas [5].
Historical Sense of Psychological Crisis (1927) or as it is known in
the West, Historical Sense of Crisis in Psychology is of great relevance to the
topic under discussion. This book marks a watershed between early Vygosky and
the Vygotsky of the cultural-historical theory. In this work (which remained
unpublished until 1982) we could find a set of direct considerations of
Vygotsky about Marxist psychology. Here is the place from the book, which is
quoted almost everywhere when the problem of Vygotsky’s theory and Marxism is
discussed.
“I do not want¼ to discover what psyche is by cutting
out a pair of quotations. I want to learn from the whole of Marx’s method how to build the science, how to
approach the investigation of the psyche.” (Vygotsky, 1982, p. 421.)
It seems that clear understanding of this formula is possible only in
wider context of Vygotsky’s considerations, presented in the text. Let us try
to restore that context in brief.
He recalls how he had once been struck by a question asked by a certain
Western scientist. The question was “What psychology do you study in
That conversation gave Vygotsky food for thought and for arguments against the term ‘Marxist psychology’.
·
Firstly, just as the theory of
·
Secondly, Vygotsky had another
argument against the term ‘Marxist psychology’:
“Marxist psychology is not a school among schools but the only true
psychology as a science. There can be no other psychology but this one”.
(Vygotsky, 1982, p. 435.)
For Vygotsky the term ‘Marxist psychology “coincided with that of scientific psychology in general
wherever and by whomsoever it might be developed” (Vygotsky, 1982, p. 435).
This might be the formula, probably the
key formula, expressing Vygotsky’s understanding of what is Marxist
psychology.
Vygotsky
rejected the way of building Marxist psychology by taking certain formulae of
dialectical laws from philosophy and explaining psychological processes and
their laws in terms of concrete manifestations of the universal laws of
dialectic. On this point he criticised K. Kornilov who was one of the
scientific leaders of Marxist psychology in 1920s.
Firstly,
Kornilov’s approach to the creation of Marxist psychology “in the light of
dialectical materialism” was quite typical for that time. To understand the
nature of consciousness was to explain it in accordance with materialism and
dialectic. The main idea was to explain the ‘dialectical’ nature of psychical
processes and laws by presenting them as examples of fundamental and universal
philosophical laws such as the law of the mutual penetration of opposites, the
law of the transformation of quantity into quality and the law of the negation
of negation. In particular, the changes in perception of figures described in
Gestalt theory were explained in accordance with the law of transformation of
quantity into quality (Kornilov, 1930, p. 255).
So,
“immediate application of the theory
of dialectical materialism to the problems of natural science, in particular to
biology and psychology, is impossible as it is impossible to apply it
immediately to history or sociology¼ Like history, sociology requires the
special mediating theory of historical materialism, which explains the
particular significance of the abstract laws of dialectical materialism for a
particular group of phenomena. Similarly, a theory of biological materialism,
or psychological materialism, as a mediating science explicating the concrete
application of the abstract tenets of dialectical materialism to a particular
domain of phenomena is indispensable.” (Vygotsky, 1982, p. 419-420.)
The problem of Marxism and psychology, Vygotsky argued, is much more
complex than the mere construction of psychology in accordance with Marxism.
Psychology needs a certain methodology-theory (meta-theory) of its own but not
one taken strictly from philosophy. For political economy, history and
sociology such a mediated meta-theory
(historical materialism) was devised by K. Marx in Capital.
In this sense psychology needs its own Capital. In this (and only in this particular but principal)
context Vygotsky argues: “In order to create such enabling theories -
methodologies in general sciences - it
is necessary to discover the essence of the given area of phenomena, the laws
of their changes, their qualitative and quantitative characteristics, their
causality; to create the categories and concepts relevant to them - in other
words, to create one’s own Capital.” (Vygotsky, 1982, p. 420.)
According to Vygotsky, the
idea is not to impose the dialectical principles on nature but to find them
there. Similarly, as Capital
was not the application of
dialectical materialism to the problems of political economy and society, the
future Capital in psychology was seen
only as the possibility of expressing
and describing its own objects and their laws but not as the application of dialectical materialism.
Consequently, the categories, concepts and laws in this Capital must be psychological
but not philosophical ones (Vygotsky, 1982, p. 420).
The conclusion of the work comes across rather like a verdict:
“Ultimately, there is no Marxist
psychology as yet. This must be seen as a historical task, not as something
given. But in the present state of affairs it is difficult to avoid the impression
that there is a considerable lack of scientific seriousness and responsibility
surrounding this appellation.” (Vygotsky, 1982, p. 433)
Bearing this in mind let us now turn to the final period of Vygotsky’s
work (1927-1934) and his famous cultural-historical theory.
A
survey of the literature on the subject demonstrates quite clearly that at
least three ideas from the cultural-historical theory may be viewed as Marxist.
These are (1) the role of human activity (practice) in mental development, (2)
social origins of mind and (3) cultural signs/symbols as ‘psychological tools’.
But do we have enough evidence for the assertion that these ideas are
exclusively Marxist? Before coming to this point let us change the angle of
analysis.
General genetic law of
development – Marxist roots?
As classical
physics is based on Newtonian laws, the theory of Vygotsky is based on the law,
called “general genetic law of cultural development”. It seems to be clear that
if we do not understand (or just misunderstand) the general law, we could
hardly understand the whole theory, based on this law. We can assume that clear
understanding of general law might
bring a new light how cultural-historical theory is connected with Marxist
philosophy. Is the general law connected with Marxist approach, or maybe there
are some other roots of it?
Here is the
formulation of the general genetic law of cultural development how it was
presented in Vygotsky’s original text
“...any function in the child’s cultural development appears on
stage twice, that is, on two planes. It firstly appears on the social plane and
then on a psychological plane. Firstly among people as an inter-psychological
category and then within the child as an intra-psychological category. This is
equally true with regard to voluntary attention, logical memory, the formation
of concepts and the development of volition.” (Vygotsky, 1983, p.145.)
It is curious
that in literature, the Western readers work with, there is slightly different
formulation.
This comes from
the Mind in Society of 1978.
"…every function in the child's…development appears twice: first, on the social level, and later, on the individual level; first between people (interpsychological), and then inside the child (intrapsychological)… (Vygotsky, 1978, p. 57)
This formulation
was quoted and repeated so many times that gradually obtained a status of
classical formulation for generations of researchers.
The other interpretation belongs to Vasilii Davydov.
Every function “appears…twice, firstly as collective, social
activity (kollektivnaya, sotsial’naya
deyatelnost) and then as individual activity (deyatelnost individualnaya)”
(Davydov, 1996, p. 24)
At first glance,
despite slight differences these two interpretations look more or less similar
and correspond to the Vygotsky’s formulation. They both emphasise the most
important aspect – social origins of mind, as fundamental in Vygotsky’s
approach to human development. Even more, giving such an interpretation, V.
Davydov directly says that here is the central point that connects Vygotsky’s
approach to Marxist tradition (Davydov, 1996, p. 24). We will come to the term
“activity” in Vygotsky’s theory later, but now let us ask whether another
interpretation of the general genetic law is possible?
To find the
answer link, to understand Vygotsky’s formulation of the law, to identify it’s
every word it is needed to know the language the formulation was written on.
Let us try to make
a step to such kind of identification.
According to
Vygotsky every function appears firstly on the social plane, among people. But
the crucial point is that the function DOES NOT and cannot appear IN the social
relations.
“…every higher mental function, before becoming internal mental function, previously was a social relation between two people”. “All mental functions are internalized social relations” (Vygotsky, 1983, p.145 -146).
So, before
becoming individual function, it was not in a social relation, it was a social
relation itself. Social relation is not the “area”, not the field, and not the
“level” where mental function appears, - the social relation itself becomes
child’s individual function – herein lies the answer.
If every higher
mental function was a social relation between two people, does it mean that
every social relation can become a mental function? Definitely not!
Nevertheless, in Vygotsky’s formulation we can find clear notion of what type
or relation can become a mental function. The point is that to understand it we
have to turn to the language of Russian culture of the beginning of 20th
century. We have to recall that Vygotsky went to psychology from the area of
humanities and culture. He belongs to the generation of “Silver Age of Russian
culture”. Theatre, poetry, arts,
literature of that period had a language of their own which was almost totally
lost after the Revolution.
In our context I mean particularly the word “category” Vygotsky uses in the formulation. What the word “category” actually means? From the times of Aristotle, especially in German classical philosophy, the category is the most abstract, the most general concept (Spirit and Matter are examples of categories). It sounds strange therefore that the mental function appears twice, first as inter-psychological category, and then as intra-psychological category. Maybe it is just a sort of metaphor, which can be easily omitted in translation?
Not at all! On
the contrary, the word “category” (which is repeated twice in the formulation
of the general law) has definite meaning. In Russian pre-revolutionary
theatre’s vocabulary the word category meant “dramatic event, collision of
characters on the stage”. Vsevolod Meierhold (famous Russian theatre director)
wrote that category is the event, which creates the whole drama (Meierhold,
1920). Sergey Eisenstein, famous film director wrote: “Category is a unit of drama”. Vygotsky was
familiar with the language of Russian theatre and arts and had to use the word
“category” to emphasize the character of the social relation, which become the
individual function. The social relation he means is not an ordinary social
relation between the two individuals. This is a social relation that it appears
as a category, i. e. as emotionally coloured and experiencing collision, the
contradiction between the two people, the dramatical event, a drama between two
individuals. Being emotionally and mentally experienced as social drama (on the
social plane) it later becomes the individual intra-psychological category.
Probably, the
best (and familiar to everybody) example here might be the case of debate
between the two people. Imagine (or just remember) that one day you met a
friend and had a debate, expressing opposite positions. Dramatical collision in
a debate, experienced by the both participants, can lead to a sort of
self-reflection. In a course of time, (for example on next morning) one of the
participants remembers the event and what he has been done and said. It could
happen like «I was wrong saying that, I made a mistake…I should not say such
sharp words…I was so aggressive and did not pay enough attention to what he
tried to say…How stupid I was yesterday…”
We see here that
the individual now experiences the same category intra-psychologically. In this
type of internal category all the mental functions of the individual are
involved (memory – “I said something rough”, emotions – “How stupid my
behaviour was, what a shame”, thinking – “I have to think it over and never
repeat such bad things”, volition – “I must stop it, I will never forget of
what I have been done. I promise to myself to be patient…”
Such emotionally
experienced collision brings radical changes to the individual’s mind, and
therefore it is a sort of act of development of mental functions – the
individual becomes different, he becomes higher and above his own behaviour.
Without internal drama, an internal category, such kind of mental changes are
hardly possible[6].
This
consideration about dramatical character of development, reflected in the word
“category” brings the following question: are there any other words and terms
in Vygotsky’s formulation, which are also of primary importance?
It seems that
words “on the stage” and “on two planes” are not metaphors, which might be
omitted or ignored. Scientific formula
of the general law of the theory is not a good place for any kind of metaphors.
Stage in Russian means “scene”, the arena, literally the place in the theatre
where actors play. Scene has two planes – the front plane (also called “the
first plane”) and the back plane (often called “the second plane[7]”). According to
theatre’s traditions, main events of the performance should happen on the front
plane of the scene (the same law we could find in visual arts). So, it means
that on the stage of our development, the category appears twice –
inter-psychologically (on the first, front plane) and then
intra-psychologically (on the second internal individual plane). Therefore
there are no two levels in development, but there are two planes on ONE stage,
two dimensions of one event.
All this gives some grounds to assert that discovering
cultural-philosophical roots of cultural-historical theory we should keep in
mind that they were not limited by Marxism – the language of Russian
cultural-philosophical tradition was the language Vygotsky perfectly spoke.
This link with Russian philosophy, culture and arts should not be
underestimated.
With this in mind let us turn to the mentioned above ideas from the
cultural-historical theory often seen as Marxist: (1) the role of human
activity (practice) in mental development, (2) social origins of mind and (3)
cultural signs/symbols as ‘psychological tools’.
Human activity and development
The prevailing opinion in modern literature is that Vygotsky’s
assertion of the role of human activity was in some sense similar to the Marx’s
well-known First Thesis on Feuerbach. A. N. Leont’ev noted:
“The importance of this category [the
category of activity] hardly needs to be emphasised. We need only recall Marx’s
famous thesis on Feuerbach, in which he said that the chief defect of earlier
metaphysical materialism was that it viewed sensuousness only as a form of
contemplation, not as human activity or practice….” (Leont’ev, 1981, p. 41.)
This
is closely connected with the long tradition of presenting the relations
between the two theories, i.e. the cultural-historical and the psychological
theories of activity. Soviet representatives of this approach look at these
theories as two historical and theoretical stages in the development of Marxist
psychology (see, for example, Davydov & Radzikhovskii, 1985; Davydov &
Zinchenko, 1989). The main point of the discussion is the role and status of
the concept of ‘activity’ in Vygotsky’s theory and the theory of activity (for
more details see Jensen, 1999; Tolman, 2001; Lektorsky, 1999; Tulviste, 1999).
The English term activity has two Russian equivalents. The first is aktivnost and the second deyatelnost. Aktivnost traditionally refers to processes in the organism or to
an active state (in contrast to a passive one). In German aktivnost is rendered by Aktivitat.
Deyatelnost is a term referring to
the practical, socially organised, object-related, goal-directed activity of an
individual (for example, labour activity is trudovaya deyatelnost).
In German deyatelnost is Tätigkeit.
Moreover (and this complicates the situation),
very often deyatelnost is used in a
sense of aktivnost (for example
‘brain activity’ is ‘deyatelnost mozga’, or ‘higher nervous activity’ is
‘visshaya nervnaya deyatelnost’). In such cases deyatelnost has nothing to do with Tätigkeit.
Very often, however, and especially in
translations of Vygotsky, these two terms are translated into English by the
same word, activity, in spite of
differences of meaning intended. This leads to numerous mistakes and
misunderstandings, particularly amongst those who work with English
translations of Vygotsky’s works.
According to the theory of A. N. Leont’ev the term deyatel’nost as the central category (Leont’ev, 1974-1975, 1978, 1981) has an
absolutely definite and concrete meaning.
For example, he wrote, “It is our position that the proper way for psychology...is
to introduce the category of object-type activity (gegenständliche
Tätigkeit)...We are speaking here about activity,
not about behaviour or the processes of nervous physiology...” (Leont’ev,
1974-1975, p. 9.) According to Leont’ev, the term Tätigkeit (deyatel’nost) should be used in contrast to Aktivität (Leont’ev, 1974-1975, p. 6;
Leont’ev, 1977, p. 75).
As for Vygotsky, our analysis shows[8] that in all of his texts between 1924 and
1927 the term deyatelnost was used
not in the sense of Tätigkeit but in
that of Aktivität, in line with
typical and traditional usage in the physiology and psychology of the time.
Vygotsky used this term in the same sense as Ivan Pavlov (higher neural
activity - vysshaya nervnaya deyatelnost),
Vladimir Bekhterev (correlative activity) and Charles Sherrington (the activity
of nervous centres). In any case I could not find in the early texts of
Vygotsky the term ‘activity’ used in the sense of Tätigkeit. This means that the widely held view that the origins of
this concept may be found in the early writings of Vygotsky (Kozulin, 1996;
Nardi, 1996) can no longer be considered beyond dispute.
As for the writings after 1927[9] the
situation looks different. Developing his cultural-historical theory Vygotsky
wrote in some cases about activity in the sense of Tätigkeit.
Summarising the analysis of texts, we may formulate three main contexts for the
use of this term by Vygotsky:
1. In the article ‘Play and its role in the
mental development of the child’ (Vygotsky, 1966/1933) he states that play is a
leading activity in early childhood. Later on in the mid 1930s this notion was
developed and transformed by A.N. Leont’ev and his collaborators into the
concept of leading activity. As
for Vygotsky,
he did not formulate this as a concept, but undoubtedly put preconditions for
it.
In contrast,
there are numerous places in his works where speech and communication are
presented as formative sources of the human mind.
Vygotsky claimed that “…speech plays an essential role in the organisation of higher mental functions.” (Vygotsky, 1978, p.23). Later he improved the position, saying that “speech, being initially the means of communication, the means of association, the means of organization of group behaviour, later becomes the basic means of thinking and of all higher mental functions, the basic means of personality formation...(Vygotsky, 1998, p. 169). As we can see this position is directly connected with the formulation of the “general genetic law of cultural development” we discussed above.
2. There is also another place where Vygotsky speaks about the role of
activity in the development of human mental functions. In the article of 1930
he discussed the particular problem of the role of labour activity in the
process of the child’s intellectual development, that is, the development of intelligence
(Vygotsky, 1930; Vygotsky, 1976). Even the most careful reader of this article
will find nothing about “activity as the substance of human
consciousness”. On the contrary there are a number of places where Vygotsky
emphasises that despite the connection between labour activity and the
development of intelligence (umstvennoe razvitie), consciousness is not
reducible to it. Labour activity was seen as just one factor of development
rather than the source.
It seems, therefore, that we do not have sufficient grounds for the
assertion that the concept of activity (deyatelnost, Tätigkeit) played an essential role in the cultural-historical
theory.
It should be also added that
by the end of the 1930s Vygotsky’s theory was under attack from A.N. Leont’ev
and his
“Vygotsky’s fundamental error is..[that] he misconstrued the Marxist conception of the historical and social determination of the human mind. Vygotsky understood the Marxist perspective idealistically...The source of mental development was thought to be communication of the subject’s mind with the cultural, ideal reality rather than his actual relationship to reality.” (Zinchenko, 1983-1984, p. 66)
Moreover, Vygotsky’s mistake
“impeded any understanding of the true, concrete, psychological source of the origin and development of...mental activity...This led Vygotsky to the idea of communication as the source and prime mover of the development of the child’s consciousness, to an idealistic understanding of communication in terms of ‘spiritual intercourse’, as speech communication rather than as the mutual relations of people with one another, relations that include their ‘material intercourse’ (Marx).” (Zinchenko, 1983-1984, p. 71)
This does not mean that P.I. Zinchenko misunderstood Vygotsky’s
approach. Rather it indicates that in 1930s nobody was under any doubt that
cultural-historical theory might have anything to do with the concept of
activity as the source of the development of the human mind.
Social origins of mind
Undoubtedly the
social origin of mind is one of the distinguishing features of Vygotsky’s
approach. It was first formulated in his early writings as follows: “Our
personality is organised according to the same model as social communication.”
(Vygotsky, 1926a, p. 178).
As for the writings of 1927-1934, in its full form this idea was presented
in the beginning of 1930s in Development
of Higher Psychological Functions (Vygotsky, 1960, p. 13-223, Vygotsky,
1981); “everything internal in higher forms was external...When we speak of a
process, ‘external’ means ‘social’. Any higher mental function was external
because it was social.” (Vygotsky, 1981, p. 162.) What was really new in
Vygotsky’s formulation was that the social world was seen not as a factor of development but as the source of the human mind.
This formulation
coincides with the famous thesis by Marx: “It is
not the consciousness of men that determines their existence but, on the
contrary, their social existence that determines their consciousness.” (Marx
,1859)
But
does this mean that it must be identified as a Marxist trait in Vygotsky’s
theory? Did Vygotsky himself considered his formula to occupy
the Marxist position? There is some evidence for that. Thus, he wrote:
“To paraphrase a well-known position
of Marx’s, we could say that the psychological nature of humans represents the
aggregate of internalised social relations
that have become functions for the individual and forms of his/her structure...
All higher mental functions are internalised social relationships... We do not
want to say that this is the meaning of Marx’s position but we see in this
position the fullest expression of that toward which the history of cultural
development leads us.…” (Vygotsky, 1981, p. 164-165).
It should be pointed out
that the idea of the social origins of mind is not originally a Marxist one. In
particular, Wilhelm Wundt propounded the notion that higher psychological
processes could only be investigated through a historical study of cultural
products such as tales, language and cultural customs. G. H. Mead, J. Dewey, E.
Durkheim, E. Cassirer and many others proceeded from the assumption that the
nature of human consciousness is determined by sociocultural factors (see, for
instance, Cole, 1995, p. 5; Maffiolo, 1993; Netchine-Grynberg, 1995). In any case, to paraphrase Marx’s Sixth Thesis on
Feuerbach does not mean to construct ‘Marxist psychology’.
Moreover,
if we take a look on this position from the perspective of “general genetic law
of development” we could find some grounds for the assertion that the idea of
the social origins of the mind had deeper (even hidden) roots in the philosophy
of “Silver Age of Russian culture”.
We have biographical data to confirm that during his university years
(1913-1916) Vygotsky attended lectures by G. G. Shpet (1879 - 1937) and
participated in his seminars on ‘ethnic psychology’. It is remarkable that the
question of the influence of the ideas of Gustav Shpet or on a wider scale of
Russian idealist philosophy on Vygotsky was not debated in Soviet literature.
Resent Russian sources on this theme are presented by works of Martsinkovskaya ( Martsinkovskaya, 1999) and Zinchenko (Zinchenko, 2003). I could add to this at least
two important points.
For political and
ideological reasons Vygotsky was not able to even mention the name of Shpet,
but he definitely was acquainted with his concept. Firstly, in his
‘ethnic’ psychology G. Shpet defended the notion of objective meaning, independent of the individual, and of ideas
realised in history. However, he pointed out that the psychological aspect is
made patent precisely in the act of their being realised by empirical subjects.
He presented the idea of combining the individual senses and social meanings
into a single structure. “A cultural phenomenon such as the expression of sense
is objective but in it, within this expression, there is also a
conscious...attitude toward this ‘sense’ and it is this attitude that is the
subject matter of psychology. Not sense, not meaning, but co-meaning
accompanying the realisation of the historical, the subjective responses and experiences,
and attitude toward it, are the subject matter of psychology.” (Shpet, 1989, p.
11). Let us compare this now with the
Vygotskian thesis:
“Initial
forms of affective-semantic formations (affektivno-smislovie obrazovaniya) of
human consciousness exist objectively outside of the separate person, they
exist in human society as products of arts.... i.e. these forms exist earlier
than individual or subjective affective-semantic formations.” (Vygotsky, 1991,
p.211)
Later Vygotsky proposed that meaning be regarded as a structural
component of the unit of analysis of the mind. Furthermore, Vygotsky considered
that the nature of the meaning is social, that the meaning is really
co-meaning, that is, generalised social relations within the culture.
Secondly, in his psychological theory Shpet defined two types of
environment - the natural and the spiritual. “There are two directions in which
the experiences of the single consciousness move through its own causality -
the natural environment and the spiritual one.” (Shpet, 1989, p. 508) According
to Shpet, neither materialistic no intellectualistic psychology is able to
describe the nature of relations and the attitude of individual consciousness
and the spiritual environment (Ibid.). This idea is remarkable from the
methodological point of view since the notion of psychological dualism and the limitations of one-sided approaches
in psychology were much criticised by Vygotsky in his Methods of Reflexological
and Psychological Investigation (1926) and later in Historical Sense of
Psychological Crisis.
We may add than the cultural-historical theory of the development of
higher mental functions worked out by Vygotsky in 1927-1928 was an attempt to
overcome traditional dualism in the psychological explanation of the mind.
Instead, it chose as its basis monistic explanations of the relations between
the man and his cultural environment. It is worth remembering that Vygotsky
used the idea of cultural environment and also the concept of two types of
development as one of the basic foundations of his theory of human
consciousness. Of course, the influence of Shpet was not a direct or strict
one. However, it demonstrates that Vygotsky was not a ‘lone thinker’. He was a
child of the intellectual and cultural environment of his time which included
more than just the philosophy of Marxism and naturalistic psychology.
Sign mediation and ‘psychological tools’
Tools
of labour, psychological tools and symbolic mediation are widely discussed as
Marxist themes in Vygotsky’s approach (see, for example, extended discussions
on this in Jones, 2000, and Zinchenko, 1995).
For
the purposes of the present article it makes sense to formulate this conception
in the following terms.
Firstly,
higher mental functions are mediated by cultural tools. Accordingly, “...the
central fact of our psychology is that of mediation.” (Vygotsky, 1982, 166)
Secondly, according to Vygotsky this type of organisation is basic to
all higher mental functions. The use of signs leads humans to a completely new
and specific structure of behaviour, breaking away from the traditions of
biological development and creating a new form of a culturally based mental
functions. (Vygotsky, 1978, p. 40.)
Finally, discussing the problem in The Development
of Higher Psychological Functions, written in the late 1920s, Vygotsky claims
that
the sign acts as an instrument of psychological activity (aktivnost in the original Russian text – N. V.), “...in a manner
analogous to the role of a tool in labour.” (Vygotsky, 1977, p. 69) This seems to be very close to the Marxist idea
of the role of tools of labour in the development of human beings.
But the point to emphasis is that the whole
picture is deeper and more complicated and requires more careful analysis.
Signs, tools of labour and
mediation
Claiming that the use of cultural signs is
analogous to the use of tools, Vygotsky stresses that in spite of the
similarity between and common features shared by these two forms of activity
there are some essential differences (Vygotsky, 1977, p. 69).
The most fundamental difference between sign
and tool is the manner of their orientation. The function of the tool is to
serve as a conductor of human influence on the object of activity (deyatelnost – N.V.). It is externally
oriented; it must exert an effect on its object. It is a means of performing
external activity (deyatelnost) aimed
at mastery over nature. By contrast, the sign changes nothing in the object of
the psychological operation. It is a means of exerting psychological influence
on behaviour, be it one’s own behaviour or that of another. It is a means of
performing internal activity directed at mastery over oneself; the sign is
internally directed…”(Vygotsky, 1982,Vol.3, p.90).
Developing this point in
Tool and Sign prepared in 1930 (and mistakenly translated as ‘Tool and Symbol’
– see Vygotsky, 1978, p.ix), he mentions that the sign is, firstly, a means towards social
contact, a way of exerting influence on others. Only later does it appear as a
means of influencing oneself (Vygotsky, 1982,Vol.3, p.144).
In other words, for Vygotsky the sign is not like
tool of labour (just as an analogue is not a synonym!). A cultural sign (for
example, a word, gesture or even traffic sign) makes sense in its being
directed towards other people. A sign is a means for conducting social
relations (in the form of communication), including the wide social context of
communication. The concrete social relations within which the child
participates in communication are the source of the human mind (including
volitional-emotional components). In other words, sign as a psychological tool
originates in the social situation of
development. Moreover, internal activity (sign-mediated mental functions,
originally social ones) is essentially different from object-oriented activity
(mediated by tools of labour) and is not derivative from it. External
(object-related) and internal (mental) activities are essentially different because of the different means of
organisation and different types of mediation involved.
“These activities are so different from one another that the nature of
the means employed in each case cannot be same.” (Vygotsky, 1982,Vol.3, p.90)
My
second thesis concerning the subject under discussion is that the view of
cultural signs as psychological tools and as the organ of an individual was
widely discussed in Russian non-Marxist philosophy at the beginning of the
twentieth century. O. Mandelshtam (Russian poet and friend of Vygotsky), G.
Shpet (pupil of Husserl), Viacheslav Ivanov (one of the fathers of Russian
symbolism), P. Florensky, A. Losev and many others wrote extensively on this
theme.
Thus, according to Pitirim Sorokin “...the sign environment forms
different types of behaviour” (Sorokin, 1920, p.184-185). In claiming that the
use of signs leads humans to a completely new and specific structure of
behaviour and the creation of new forms of culturally based mental function,
was Vygotsky closer to Marx than to non-Marxist P. Sorokin? At the same time,
in claiming that the cultural sign is a mean of social communication, was
Vygotsky closer to P. Sorokin (who wrote that “connection of the individuals
with the same symbols connects them to each other”) than to Marx? (Ibid, p.
323).
In distinguishing between
two types of signals in terms of natural and social (signs) was Vygotsky closer
to Marx than to G. Shpet?[10].
Finally, when speaking of the role of the word as a tool of mind was Vygotsky
referring to the famous thesis of Marx or was he just repeating the position of
P. Florensky who wrote that the word is amphibian, a mediator between inner and
external realities (Florensky, 1990, p. 280)[11]?
Some final remarks
Discussing the problem of
Marxist and non-Marxist aspects of the cultural-historical psychology of L. S.
Vygotsky we should take into consideration at least two important
circumstances.
1. It was not only Marxism which influenced Vygotsky. He
was a child of the Silver Age of Russian culture and philosophy and the
influence of this should not be underestimated. He tried
to find answers to the questions concerning issues such as the individual and
the world, personality and consciousness, mind and body, thought and speech,
culture and nature, in other words, the same issues which had tormented
contemporary Russian writers, poets and philosophers.
Consequently,
some traits in Vygotsky’s theory, traditionally considered as Marxist – such as
the concept of the social origins of mind or sign as psychological tool – also
might have deeper and wider roots in works of Shpet, Florensky, Blonsky,
Sorokin and Meierhold. For political and ideological reasons Vygotsky was
not able to even mention some of these names during Soviet times. Yet in his
writings one can hear these ‘voices of culture’, often indirectly but
unmistakably.
2. As for Marxism as such, it was not something like
“holy cow” for Vygotsky. During all three periods of his creative evolution
Vygotsky had different approaches to what was true Marxist psychology and how
it should be built. The final formula of his search could be found in his own
words that the term ‘Marxist psychology’ “coincided with
that of scientific psychology in
general, wherever and by whomsoever it might be developed” (Vygotsky, 1982, p.
435). But by the 1930s Marxism was increasingly seen as a sort of ‘scientific
ideology’. Its leading principle was expressed not by the formula “true
scientific psychology can be called Marxist psychology”, but by “the Marxist
psychology is the only scientific psychology.” The theory of activity (in
contradistinction to Vygotsky) identified itself as Marxist psychology. Any
other theories (including Vygotsky’s) were viewed as non-scientific and even
anti-scientific.
In any
case, when uncovering the problem of the relation between Marxism and Vygotsky
we must take into account the dramatic and even tragic character of the
relation. In saying that “Vygotsky was more than happy to call himself a
Marxist.” (Toulmin, 1978), we should also add that it was a mournful happiness.
Literature
Artamonov, V.
Asmolov, A. G. (1998). Vygotsky today: On the verge of non-classical psychology.
Bakhurst, D. (1991). Consciousness
and revolution in Soviet philosophy: From the Bolsheviks to Evald Ilyenkov.
Bruner, J. (1987). Prologue to the English Edition. In R. Rieber &.
A. Carton (Eds.). The collected works of
L. S. Vygotsky. Volume 1. Problems of general psychology.
Cole, M. & Scribner, S. (1978). Introduction. In L. S. Vygotsky. Mind and society: The development of higher
psychological processes.
Cole, M. (1995). Kulturnie mehanizmy razvitiya. Voprosy Psihologii, 3, 5-20.
Davydov, V. V. & Radzikhovskii, L. A. (1985). Vygotsky's theory and the activity oriented approach in psychology. In
J. Wertsch (Ed.), Culture, communication
and cognition: Vygotskian perspectives.
Davydov, V. V. & Zinchenko, V. P. (1989). Vygotsky's contribution
to the development of psychology. Soviet
Psychology, 27 (2), 22-36.
Davydov, V. V. (1996). Poniatie deyatelnosti kak
osnovanie issledovanii nauchnoi shkoli Vygotskogo [Concept of activity as
foundation of research in the scientific
Elhammoumi, M. (2001). Lost - or merely domesticated?
The boom in socio-historicocultural theory emphasises some concepts, overlooks
others. In S. Chaiklin (Ed.), The theory
and practice of cultural-historical psychology.
Etkind, A. M. (1994). More on L.
S. Vygotsky: forgotten texts and undiscovered contexts. Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, 32 (6), 22-36.
Florensky, P. (1990). Sochineniya
[The works].
Jensen, U. J. (1999). Categories on activity theory: Marx's philosophy
just-in-time. In S. Chaiklin, M. Hedegaard, & U.J. Jensen (eds.), Activity theory and social practice:
Cultural-historical approach.
Jones, P.E. (2000). The dialectics of the ideal and symbolic mediation.
In V. Oittinen (Ed.), Evald Ilyenkov's
philosophy revisited,
Jones, P.E. (2001). The ideal in cultural-historical activity theory:
Issues and perspectives. In S. Chaiklin
(Ed.), The theory and practice of cultural-historical psychology.
Kornilov, K. (1930). Psychology in the light of dialectical
materialism. In C. Murchison (Ed.), Psychologies in the 1930s.
Kozulin, A. (1996). The concept of activity in Soviet psychology:
Vygotsky, his disciples and critics. In H. Daniels (Ed.), An introduction to Vygotsky.
Lee, B. (1985). Intellectual
origins of Vygotsky's semiotic analysis. In J. V. Wertsch (Ed.), Culture, communication and cognition:
Vygotskian perspectives.
Lektorsky, V. A. (1999). Historical change of the
notion of activity: Philosophical presuppositions. In S. Chaiklin, M.
Hedegaard, & U.J. Jensen (eds.),
Activity theory and social practice: Cultural-historical approach.
Leont'ev, A. A. (1996). Foreword. In Antologia gumannoi pedagogiki. Vygotskii [Anthology of human pedagogics].
Leont'ev, A. A. (2003). Foreword. In L. S. Vygotsky. Psihologiya razvitiya
cheloveka [Psychology of development of man].
Leont'ev, A. N. (1974-1975) The problem of activity in psychology. Soviet Psychology, 2 (13), 4- 33.
Leont'ev, A.N. (1977). Deyatelnost.
Soznanie. Lichnost [Activity,
consciousness and personality].
Leont'ev, A. N. (1978). Activity,
consciousness and personality.
Leont'ev, A. N. (1981). Problems of activity in
psychology. In J. Wertsch (Ed.), The
concept of activity in Soviet psychology. New-York, Sharp
Leont'ev, A. N. (1982). Predislovie. O tvorcheskom puti L. S.
Vygotskogo [Foreword. On Vygotsky’s creative evolution]. In L. S. Vygotsky, Sobranie sochinenii, Vol. 1,
Leont'ev, A. N. & Luria, A. R. (1968). The psychological ideas of
L. S. Vygotsky. In B. B. Wolman (Ed.). Historical
roots of contemporary psychology.
Maffiolo, D. (1993). From a social to a cultural approach to the study
of cognitive activities: The fundamental role of semiotic systems. European Journal of Psychology of Education,
8 (4), 487-500.
Martsinkovskaya
T. D.(1999) Problema esteticheskogo peresivaniya v kontseptsii psihologii
sotsialnogo bytia G. G. Shpeta. [The problem of aesthetic experience in G. G.
Shpet’s concept of social being]. Voprosy
psihologii, 6, 119-127
Meierhold, V
(1920). Teatralnii slovar.
[Dictionary of theatre].
Nardi, B. (Ed.). (1996). Context
and consciousness: Activity theory and human-computer interaction.
Netchine-Grynberg, G. (1995). The functionality of cognition according
to Cassirer, Meyerson, Vygotsky, and Wallon: Toward the roots of the concept of
cognitive tool. In I. Lubek, R. van
Hezewijk, G. Pheterson & Ch. Tolman (Eds.), Trends and issues in theoretical psychology.
Newman, F. & Holzman, L. (1993). Lev Vygotsky: Revolutionary scientist.
Radzikhovskii, L. A. (1979b). Osnovnie
etapy nauchnoi raboty Vygotskogo. [Fundamental stages in Vygotsky's
scientific work]. Doctoral (Kandidatskaya) Dissertation,
Seve,
L. (1999). Quelles contradictions? A propos de Piaget, Vygotki et Marx. In Y. Clot (ed.), Acec Vygotski.
Shpet, G. (1989).
Sochineniya [The Works].
Shpet, G. (1990).
Germenevtika i ee problemi [Hermeneutics
and its probems]. Kontekst.
Sorokin, P. (1920). Sistema sotsiologii. [System of sociology]
Vol.
1.
Tolman, C. W. (2001). The origins of activity as a
category in the philosophies of Kant, Fichte, Hegel and Marx. In S. Chaiklin
(Ed.), The theory and practice of
cultural-historical psychology.
Toulmin, S. (1978). The Mozart in psychology.
Tudge, J. (1999). Discovering
Vygotsky: A historical and development approach. In
Tulviste,
P. (1999). Activity as explanatory principle in cultural psychology. In S.
Chaiklin, M. Hedegaard, & U.J. Jensen (eds.), Activity theory and social practice: Cultural-historical approach.
Van der Veer, R. & Valsiner, J. (1991). Understanding Vygotsky: A quest for synthesis.
Veresov, N. (2000). Vygotsky, Ilyenkov and Mamardashvili
-Towards a monistic theory of mind (methodological notes). In V. Oittinen (Ed.)
Evald Ilyenkov’s Philosophy Revisited..
Kikimora Publishers, p. 131-145
Vygodskaya, G. & Lifanova, T (1996). Lev Semenovich Vygotskii: Zizn, tvorchestvo,
shtrihi k portretu. [Lev Semenovich Vygotsky: life, creativity, traits of
portrait]
Vygotsky, L. S. (1925) Soznanie kak problema psihologii povedenia.
[Cosciousness as a problem in psychology of behaviour] In K. N. Kornilov (Ed.).
Psihologia i Marksizm.
Moscow-Leningrad: Gosizdat, pp. 175-198.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1926a). Metodika reflexologicheskogo i
psihologicheskogo issledovaniya. [Methods of reflexological and psychological
investigation]. In K. N. Kornilov (Ed.). Problemy
sovremennoi psihologii.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1926b). Pedagogicheskaya
psihologiya. [Pedagogical psychology].
Vygotsky, L. S. (1930). O sviazi mezdu trudovoi deyatelnostiu i
intellektualnim razvitiem rebenka [On connection between labour activity and
intellectual development in child]. Pedologia,
5/6, 588-596
Vygotsky, L. S. (1960).
Razvitie vyschih psihicheskih funktsii [Development of higher mental
functions].
Vygotsky, L. S.
(1966/1933). Igra i ee rol v psihicheskom razvitii rebenka [Play and its role
in the mental development of the child]. Voprosy
psihologii [Questions in psychology], 6,
pp. 62-76. (In Russian). Translated as Vygotsky, L. S. (1967). Play and its
role in the mental development of the child. Soviet. Psychology. N.Y, V. 3. and
The role of play in development. In: Vygotsky, L. S. (1978) Mind in society, Harvard University
Press, p. 92-104
Vygotsky, L. S. (1976). O sviazi mezdu trudovoi deyatelnostiu i
intellektualnim razvitiem rebenka [On connection between labour activity and
intellectual development in child]. Defektologia,
6, 3-8.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1977). The development of higher psychological
functions. Soviet Psychology, 3 (15),
60-73.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in
society: the development of higher psychological processes.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1979). Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of
behaviour. Soviet Psychology, 4, 3-35.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1981). The genesis of higher mental functions. In J.W. Wertsch (Ed.). The concept of activity in Soviet psychology.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1982). Sobranie sochinenii [The collected
works].
Vygotsky, L.
S. (1983). Sobranie sochinenii [The collected works].
Vygotsky, L. S. (1991). Pedagogicheskaya
psihologia [Pedagogical psychology].
Vygotsky, L. S. (1994). The methods of reflexological and psychological
investigation. In R. Van der Veer & J. Valsiner (Eds.), The Vygotsky reader.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1997). Educational
psychology.
Vygotsky, L.S. (1998). Collected
works. Vol. 5.
Vygotsky, L. S.
(1999). Consciousness as a problem in the psychology of behaviour. In: N. Veresov. Undiscovered Vygotsky. Peter Lang,
p.251-281
Wertsch, J. V. (Ed.). (1981).
The concept of activity in Soviet
psychology.
Wertsch, J. V. (1983). The role of semiosis in L. S. Vygotsky's theory
of human cognition. In B. Bain (Ed.). The
sociogenesis of language and human conduct.
Wertsch, J. V. (1985a). Introduction. In J. Wertsch (Ed.). Culture, communication and cognition:
Vygotskian perspectives.
Yaroshevsky, M. (1992). L. S. Vygotsky i Marksizm v sovetskoi psihlogii
[Vygotsky and Marxism in Soviet
psychology]. Psychologicheskii Journal,
13(5), 84-99.
Zinchenko, P. I. (1939). Problema neproizvolnogo
zapominaniya. Nauchnie zapiski
Kharkovskogo gosudarstvennogo pedagogicheskogo instituta instrannih yasikov.
Vol. 1, p. 145-187. Translated as Zinchenko, P. I. (1983-1984). The problem
of involuntary memory. Soviet psychology,
2, 55-111.
Zinchenko,
V. P. (1995). Cultural-historical psychology and the psychological theory of
activity: retrospect and prospect. In J. V. Wertsch, P. del
Zinchenko, V (2003). Mysl I slovo. Podhody L. S.
Vygotskogo i G.G. Shpeta [Thought and word. Approaches of L. S. Vygotsky and G.
G. Shpet] Psihologicheskaya nauka I
obrazovanie, 4, p. 31-39)
* A debt of gratitude is owed to Mariane Hedegaard who has taken the
time to reed and comment on this paper. I would like to thank Professor Pentti
Hakkarainen, from
[1] Thus, A. M. Etkind notes that in Pedagogical Psychology "Vygotsky quoted the ideas of Lev Trotsky by pages" and that "in the 1991 edition, edited by V. V. Davydov, the quotation marks are removed from the quotation and the name of Lev Trotsky is left out. The authors of... an American monograph on Vygotsky (van der Veer & Valsiner, 1991), trusting Davydov, quoted this text after its publication as the creation of Vygotsky himself". (Etkind, 1994, p. 29-30.)
[2] “Silver Age of Russian culture” is well known period of Renaissance of arts and culture in Russian Empire at the beginning of the XXth century, tragically interrupted by Bolsheviks in 1917. Vygotsky-the student was one of the most active participants of that cultural space. His first published articles were on literary criticism and theatre (for more details see Van der Veer & Valsiner, 1991; Vygodskaya & Lifanova, 1996).
[3] In this paper all translations from Russian sources are mine – Nikolai Veresov
[4] In English translation of the article "adaptive reactions" was translated as "adaptive
activities". (Vygotsky, 1979, p.68).
[5]I can only explain this in such a way that Davydov and Radzikhovskii
have access to an unknown version of Vygotsky's article, which differs from
both Russian editions as well as from the English ones.
[6] In other place of the same text Vygotsky uses the word “drama” directly. “From here comes, that one of the central principles of our work is experimental unfolding of higher mental process into the drama, which happened between the people” (Vygotsky, 1983, p.145)
[7] I could compare this with “the role of second plane” in contemporary cinema.
[8] Me made this analysis on the basis of Vygotsky's complete bibliography made by T. Lifanova (Vygodskaya & Lifanova, 1996, p. 390-418)
[9] We focused our text analysis on the Lifanova's list with special
emphasis to "The problem of the
Cultural Development of the Child" (1928), "The History of the
Development of the Higher mental functions" (1983), "The Development
of Higher Psychological Functions" (1960, 1977, 1981), "The
Instrumental Method in Psychology" (1981), "Concrete Human
Psychology" (1989), "Tool and the Sign in a Child's Development
(1960), and, of course, in his Magnus
Opus "Thinking and Speech" (1934, 1962, 1986).
[10] In his book of 1920, G. Shpet formulates in the following way: "There are two categories of symbols...natural and social" (Shpet, 1990, p. 428).
[11] I could give more details on the connections of Vygotsky and Russian philosophical tradition, but because of lack of space see Veresov, 2000.